Monday, April 28, 2008

Re: Response to me (part 2)

This will conclude my response to PJ--for now--after which I will allow him to make a rebuttal. I've attempted to keep my response brief. Naturally, I've failed. Should there be something which you believe I did not address sufficiently, do let me know so that I may revisit it.

Ah, but human nature does change and with it, the social world. Our "first," material-biological nature is the product of evolutionary forces, of course; but morality is a relatively new phenomenon, in the vast time-scales of the life sciences, and it can only emerge for beings who develop our kind of social "second" nature.

This strikes me as peculiar, and seems to add more questions than it provides answers. Supposing I accept your premise—which I cannot—several questions arise. I've given you more than enough to chew on without compelling you to answer all of them, but they are worthy of consideration. Is human nature equal in all its members, or are some humans “more equal than others?” Does one's moral code depend on one's place in the ever-evolving human nature? Is human nature moving towards something, away from something, or are these fluctuations essentially trivial in the grand scheme of things? I sense much Wells in you.

If you could provide a list of differing human natures and an ethic which would apply differently to two of them I would greatly appreciate it.

Rather, selfhood can only be cashed out in terms of irreducibly social commitments and identifications.

This seems to suggest that man draws his worth from those men around him. But if those men are similarly without value, whence does this value arise? If you sum zero infinitely, it is still zero. Unless man has worth—in my view because God bestows him with it—mankind is effectively worthless.

The "glass" is a mirror, the idea being that, reflecting on God, we are reflecting on ourselves without realizing that that is what we are doing.

Only if God's revelation isn't really what we claim. I think it mighty unfair to our ancestors to insist, looking down upon them from several centuries of perhaps not entirely worthless experience, that they were merely reflecting on ourselves—and projecting onto God? To revisit Moses, theoretically he could have been reflecting on himself, though one wonders why on earth he would insist that he should go confront Pharaoh over his Jewish problem. In addition, as Vox Day points out, “I Am Who Am” may be a silly thing for a bush to say, but it's also a silly story for a nomad existing several centuries before Christ to invent.

To be utilitarian, a theory must advance a single, comprehensive, conception of the good -- in terms of utility -- and then it must stipulate that the moral worth of an action is determined by the extent to which it maximizes that good. I, on the contrary, believe that there are a plurality of real goods and that we have to give priority to ourselves and the people close to us (although I won't directly defend the latter part of this claim, unless you're especially interested).

While I greatly enjoyed Atlas Shrugged, I'm no objectivist, so I won't fault you for believing we have some duty to those close to us. Still, while your plurality of goods makes a certain amount of sense—natural law theorists similarly posit a number of goods: knowledge, procreation, life, and sociability, if memory serves—it begs a question. I'm afraid it is one I have asked before: whence do these goods arise? It leaves you with something of a Euthyphro dilemma on your hands. The natural law theory points to God as the source of all good. Your goods point to... either satisfaction—which would be utilitarian—or... what?

The satisfactions of helping someone solve a difficult problem, of listening to a symphony, and of enjoying a glass of fine wine, for instance, are qualitatively distinct in such a way as to preclude quantitative comparisons.

Well, you could help someone with the problem of what on earth is to be done with his fine wine while listening to a symphony, but I agree. The problem is when we consider such acts which are not morally permissible ones. For instance, in choosing whether to violate a virgin, murder an old woman, or rob a bank, are we similarly left with the problem of quantifying our satisfaction. But if we add, to the list of options, “or read a Walker Percy novel”, of course you should pick Percy, but not because he is an excellent writer, but because this is your only permissible moral choice. Even if one derives no satisfaction from reading the novel--especially if one doesn't know how to read English very well--this is still the morally correct choice.

Now, obviously no one would ever be confronted with these bizarre choices, save perhaps in a novel, but the point is that the satisfaction which is implicitly posited as the determining factor in considering what one should do. No matter how much satisfaction our hypothetical character may derive from ravishing a virgin, moral standards prevent him from acting on what is essentially a utilitarian principle. Our virgin thanks him.

This isn't to say that all decisions are equally good or that it doesn't matter what one does with one's life, only that the relevant standards must be supplied by the individual's conception of "the good life," her sense of who she is and who she wants to become.

I don't wish to be more of a jerk than I've already been, but if we return to our virgin, if I wish to go about, being the best rapist I can be, what standards would you posit to compel me to do otherwise?

Notice, now, that working toward the good life requires a minimal kind of self-consciousness: it is not just a matter of activating pleasure-centers in the brain, but of achieving describable goals -- however these may shift about in the course of a life. It is, in other words, a matter of *self*-actualization.

You are pronouncing judgment against merely activating pleasure-centers in the brain. Well and good, but on what grounds? Michel Onfray, from the little I know of him, would vociferously disagree; he would assert that you are preventing him from attaining self-actualization. In addition, if self-actualization is the good at which man's life is aimed—yes I know, you say there are a number of goods, but unless I am mistaken, I see here a contradiction—then you are stating that man is the rule by which all things are to be measured. This makes sense from a God-less perspective, but it rather deflates any chance of promulgating a coherent and lucid system of ethics.

Furthermore, it is up for social negotiation whether my deeds fall under the act-description I invoke and whether I live up to the identity I claim for myself.

Again, I may be making mistakes here, but I'm unclear as to how society may dictate to me whether or not I am progressing towards self-actualization. If society has a claim to my behavior, fine, I suppose, but this can very certainly threaten my ability to become the self that I desire to be.

For example, there is no intelligible sense in which someone might "really" be a good professor in spite of his inability to capture the attention and imagination of his students and colleagues.

Sure there is. Perhaps his students are all dunderheads, or that they don't give a whit for the subject matter, or they're distracted by text messages from their friends. There are any number of, if not professors, writers who “succeed” despite an inability to write well. Those who pen harlequin romance novels are well-received by their audience, and I suppose we could bequeath upon them the title of Producer of Much Emotional Porn and Other Sundry Nonsense, or some such twaddle, but I don't think you or I would take the verdict of their audience without a grain of salt.

To be clear, what is important is not that there always be another person physically there affirming your success to you, but only that the standards by which you assess yourself are essentially social standards.

And again, I reject this. Moby Dick was very poorly received when it was written. If memory serves, some French interest revived the piece, and placed it in the pantheon of great American literature. Now, on the one hand, the social standards which Melville could have used to determine his worth as a writer failed him. On the other, one could argue that the verdict of posterity was essentially a social one, which is true; but then one would be forced to conclude that Melville was a good writer only because people rediscovered his book, and not because he was, in fact, a good writer.

Without shared social practices, standards, and ideals, human life would be reduced to a pathological hedonism. We have an obligation, therefore, to maintain the most fundamental of these networks -- the conditions of lawfulness itself -- by respecting the dignity of the self-conscious agents in which these networks subsist.

This strikes me as a particularly poor argument. Anarchy is undesirable, therefore, we must have law. You peer into the abyss, and because you don't like what you see, you embrace an ethical code which is neither clear not compelling. I don't think poorly of you because of this decision, but an emotional aversion to hedonism isn't the best base upon which to rest a system of ethics.

I eagerly await your response, and thank you again for continuing in this quest for truth.

4 comments:

Doom said...

I cannot yet focus enough to dig through this. Pardon my sad state. However, I am looking for something of which I may begin partaking. So, gather thine whits and write thee hie. Or something less lame than that. Oh, and hello.

A Wiser Man Than I said...

It's quite alright. This sort of thing doesn't excite everyone.

I hope life is treating you well.

Doom said...

It isn't a matter of excite. I just feel overwhelmed and too far behind to catch up. As my mental gears would work and spark, it would throw out thoughts that would be juvenile to the current debate. I have put a great deal on my plate, one more heavy thing is too much. Your work DOES excite me, even when you are wrong *laughs at us both, for many reasons, though a kindly laugh*

Life is indeed treating me well. I am trying to return the favor. Be well.

PJ said...

Hi Eric,

Sorry for another substantial delay in my response. I was somewhat frustrated to see from your questions that I hadn't communicated myself very effectively in previous posts. So I procrastinated for a while thinking about how to best address this. Part of the problem, I think, is that we're debating not so much facts as "paradigms," that is, the interpretive frameworks in which we situate facts and in terms of which they acquire their peculiar significance. I'm not sure whether or not this is a helpful heuristic, but, read on, and we'll find out.

PJ (earlier): Ah, but human nature does change and with it, the social world. Our "first," material-biological nature is the product of evolutionary forces, of course; but morality is a relatively new phenomenon, in the vast time-scales of the life sciences, and it can only emerge for beings who develop our kind of social "second" nature.

Eric: This strikes me as peculiar, and seems to add more questions than it provides answers. Supposing I accept your premise—which I cannot—several questions arise. I've given you more than enough to chew on without compelling you to answer all of them, but they are worthy of consideration. Is human nature equal in all its members, or are some humans “more equal than others?” Does one's moral code depend on one's place in the ever-evolving human nature? Is human nature moving towards something, away from something, or are these fluctuations essentially trivial in the grand scheme of things? I sense much Wells in you.

PJ: This model poses a lot of questions, I agree. Some of them have clear answers while others remain controversial. What we need to determine, however, is not which model relieves our philosophical anguish, but which model provides the best description of reality. Maybe you've already explained this, but what do you think human nature is? And how do you know that the features you select are part of nature rather than the historical accomplishments of human culture? Why does it matter? How close some action is to our natural drives strikes me as largely irrelevant for assessing its ethical status. Disgust and empathy are equally natural, after all; rape and the consummation of a marriage are the same act from a strictly "natural" point of view. What matters is the context and the situation, and these are of our own making (not as individual agents, of course, but as a historical community).

Eric: If you could provide a list of differing human natures and an ethic which would apply differently to two of them I would greatly appreciate it.

PJ: I find the term "human nature" to be deeply problematic. On the one hand, we clearly do share a similar set of biological features, and, to a large extent, these determine the kinds of life available to us. On the other hand, the values attached to different practices and modes of life have an economy largely autonomous of our biological nature, and this is the realm in which we exercise our freedom and exist as ethical beings. So I prefer to focus on society, and to look for answers to ethical and moral questions in terms of the individual's embeddedness in her historical society.

PJ (earlier): Rather, selfhood can only be cashed out in terms of irreducibly social commitments and identifications.

Eric: This seems to suggest that man draws his worth from those men around him. But if those men are similarly without value, whence does this value arise? If you sum zero infinitely, it is still zero. Unless man has worth—in my view because God bestows him with it—mankind is effectively worthless.

PJ: Value emerges with consciousness: out of nature. As soon as you have an animal with what philosophers call "intentionality" -- the directionality of consciousness, its aboutness -- this, together with simple biological drives, gives you value. I distinguish water from gravel, and I happily move to drink it. VoilĂ ! The appearance of a metaphysical impasse, an unbridgeable gulf between fact and value, is the consequence of an improbably mechanistic conception of nature. (How this value gets distributed and achieves its relative autonomy, of course, is a far thornier question, but hardly intractable.)

PJ (earlier): The satisfactions of helping someone solve a difficult problem, of listening to a symphony, and of enjoying a glass of fine wine, for instance, are qualitatively distinct in such a way as to preclude quantitative comparisons.

Eric: Well, you could help someone with the problem of what on earth is to be done with his fine wine while listening to a symphony, but I agree. The problem is when we consider such acts which are not morally permissible ones. [...T]he point is that the satisfaction which is implicitly posited as the determining factor in considering what one should do. No matter how much satisfaction our hypothetical character may derive from ravishing a virgin, moral standards prevent him from acting on what is essentially a utilitarian principle. Our virgin thanks him.

PJ: We can address rape from both an ethical perspective (oriented around the good life, which, again, is not the same as utility) and a moral perspective (concerned with the constraints to which we must demand universal commitment). Ethically, raping people promotes violence that's likely to spill back into your life unexpectedly, it's going to feed into all kinds of destructive cycles, and is massively unlikely to contribute to a fulfilling human life. Rapists suffer from a confused conception of the good life. The satisfactions of nonconsensual sex are hollow and fleeting. One could expand on this theme at length with details tailored to the individual case. What you're concerned about, however, is not deciding whether to commit rape, but in establishing a normative framework from within which we can unequivocally condemn rape. But rape is a clear violation of human dignity and falls neatly into the Kantian normative sieve, on which more below.

PJ (earlier): Notice, now, that working toward the good life requires a minimal kind of self-consciousness: it is not just a matter of activating pleasure-centers in the brain, but of achieving describable goals -- however these may shift about in the course of a life. It is, in other words, a matter of *self*-actualization.

Eric: You are pronouncing judgment against merely activating pleasure-centers in the brain.

PJ: No -- and this is important -- I'm not. My claim is phenomenological; I take myself to be describing a matter of fact. The good life, which we all seek, however we may conceive it, is not pursued in terms of neural bliss. We pursue intelligible goals and projects, however inarticulate they may be in our daily lives. The hedonistic project of maximizing pleasure is self-defeating: we maximize pleasure by behaving as though we were committed to shared, external goods. Pleasure is not what life is about. Fulfillment happens at the "second nature" level of culture and society, of language and shared values.

PJ (earlier): Furthermore, it is up for social negotiation whether my deeds fall under the act-description I invoke and whether I live up to the identity I claim for myself.

Eric: Again, I may be making mistakes here, but I'm unclear as to how society may dictate to me whether or not I am progressing towards self-actualization. If society has a claim to my behavior, fine, I suppose, but this can very certainly threaten my ability to become the self that I desire to be.

PJ: You determine for yourself, inasmuch as you determine anything for yourself, who you want to be. We each have our own conception of the good life. The point is that this conception cannot be formed in a vacuum. Whether I want to be a good husband and father, or a brilliant professor, or a wealthy businessman, I can only assess my achievements with reference to public standards. These standards are open to revision, if they don't measure what they claim to; but, to be effective, criticism must develop from within. Anyone who attempts to reform his marriage dynamic to accord with the logic of his successful business practices is headed for disaster, as with the converse. This general point applies even to religious ideals. Someone who wants to live like Jesus, for instance, can only do this by modeling himself on and assessing himself against the ideals of a shared religious tradition.

PJ (earlier): To be clear, what is important is not that there always be another person physically there affirming your success to you, but only that the standards by which you assess yourself are essentially social standards.

Eric: And again, I reject this. Moby Dick was very poorly received when it was written. If memory serves, some French interest revived the piece, and placed it in the pantheon of great American literature. Now, on the one hand, the social standards which Melville could have used to determine his worth as a writer failed him. On the other, one could argue that the verdict of posterity was essentially a social one, which is true; but then one would be forced to conclude that Melville was a good writer only because people rediscovered his book, and not because he was, in fact, a good writer.

PJ: What's important here is that Melville was working within an established, novelistic genre, however much he may have transformed it with his genius. You can be sure that he was measuring himself, with some degree of self-consciousness, against the work of his canonical predecessors. This is what I mean when I say that it's not important to have other people there telling you how awesome you are. Even in isolation, you're still working in an essentially social paradigm, i.e., in accord with or in opposition to unavoidable norms and values that are themselves the product or achievement of your historical society. But I'm rather confused: Where do you think we get our literary standards?

PJ (earlier): Without shared social practices, standards, and ideals, human life would be reduced to a pathological hedonism. We have an obligation, therefore, to maintain the most fundamental of these networks -- the conditions of lawfulness itself -- by respecting the dignity of the self-conscious agents in which these networks subsist.

Eric: This strikes me as a particularly poor argument. Anarchy is undesirable, therefore, we must have law. You peer into the abyss, and because you don't like what you see, you embrace an ethical code which is neither clear not compelling. I don't think poorly of you because of this decision, but an emotional aversion to hedonism isn't the best base upon which to rest a system of ethics.

PJ: This isn't an argument from emotion or utility, it's an argument from the social ontology of value. Value emerges naturally together with preference-bearing organisms. At this primitive stage, however, values remain very much determined by biology; what is good is what satisfies natural drives, and what's bad is what causes pain. This life, moreover, is not what we would describe as a fulfilling existence. To elaborate on this and to show how we begin to achieve an autonomous world of value, I quote from a paper I wrote on Hegel's Phenomenology, of which I sent you a copy a few weeks ago:


"This demonstration begins with the concept of a primitive self-consciousness existing in the simple self-certainty of its natural desires, for which the world is just a collection of finite objects for consumption (174). This is already to say that our natural self-consciousness endows the objects of its world with a determinate meaning that they do not have independently of our self-conscious activity. An apple, for instance, does not appear in the perceptual field as an indifferent sense-object. An apple is food. It presents itself to be consumed. Although the usefulness of objects may not be obvious from their appearance, our primitive ancestors lived in families or clans and so were able to educate their desire by learning from experience and passing on to one another the best way to survive (182-184). The details of this arrangement are not important for our project. What we need to see is how this harmonious natural order necessarily breaks down in experience.

"The basic problem is that natural self-consciousness is a perpetual cycle of desire, and, in a finite world, conflict is inevitable. Let’s take as an example a particularly lush valley, in which two family clans would like to camp. For both clans, the valley has the meaning “mine.” “Mine,” of course, does not exist in the empirical world. Property is a social institution; I cannot meaningfully possess anything except by the sanction of another self-consciousness. There is no empirical fact to which we can appeal to resolve this dispute. Our conflict, then, which begins in natural desire, transforms itself into a spiritual battle of prestige. Not just the valley, but also the identity, legitimacy, and authority of self-consciousness are at stake in this dispute (cf. 178). Each self-consciousness effectively demands that the other recognize its *right* to the object (187), and our rights are radically underdetermined by the natural world. They are completely non-empirical; yet we cannot help asserting them in our activity. The problem is that our clans lack the mediating institutions to peacefully resolve their dispute. They have only physical force and the threat thereof. If neither backs down, battle to the death ensues.

"But no one wins a battle to death. The nominal victor is thrown back, unrecognized, into the cycle of natural desire. By its willingness to go to the death for its values, self-consciousness effectively demonstrates its independence from the natural teleology of self- or species-preservation. But it also learns that its freedom cannot be abstracted from natural life, and so the best that natural self-consciousness can do is to submit to the will of the stronger and enter into his service. The victorious consciousness, then, maintains Lordship by keeping his Bondsman under threat of death. With his very life dependent upon the approbation of the Lord, self-consciousness is able to focus completely upon doing the Lord’s work, and this effectively frees the Bondsman from his servitude to natural desire: the apples he picks now belong to the Lord (190-194).

"This, then, is Hegel’s imaginative reconstruction of the logic by which society necessarily emerges as an object for self-consciousness from a nature to which it is not reducible (cf. 444). Conflict forces us to assume new attitudes and projects that would not be possible for a consciousness harmoniously submerged in its natural environment. We are compelled by the social structure of experience to adopt a critical stance with regard to the customs governing our lives."


This is only the opening scene of a lengthy social drama reconstructed by Hegel in the Phenomenology of Spirit, but it is quite important for its role in setting the stage for the rest of the argument. There's nothing supernatural about value; it comes with conscious life. The social structure of experience shapes and constrains the kind of meaningful world we project with our actions. New situations generate new values, and these subsist only in our shared commitment. This commitment, however, is extraordinarily deep, ontological even: selfhood is socio-historically shaped down to the very core. There is no "true self" who could ever look down into the abyss of a world without social norms to recoil in horror. It's simply impossible. The only basis for our horror is itself value-ridden in a way that contradicts the original hypothesis. The self -- that is, the "I," who speaks and acts and to whom we can impute moral responsibility -- is not a discrete natural or metaphysical entity. It is a more or less stable configuration of commitments and identifications, all of which exist only at the level of social reality. Even our biological needs are socially modified and may in some cases be renounced altogether.

I'm afraid that I've once again worn myself out without directly addressing what you take to be the central moral issue of how we must, categorically, act. But this is partly tactical (or at least this what I'm telling myself, now that I feel I've written enough for the day). I say this because, as mentioned at the beginning, I believe that our disagreement is not so much about facts as it is about the paradigms within which facts present themselves. My idea here -- forgive me if this sounds condescending -- is that your conception of morality and your desire such a rigid moral code is the result of an inadequate paradigm, and that when you come to appreciate the naturalistic origins of value and the consequent role of social history and recognitional networks in our ethical life, that your original problem will be transformed. Or, even if you're not ultimately convinced, I least hope you'll be able to understand why I think this is the case.

Cheers,
PJ